Kant's Political Theory (2): Determinative Articles
The full subtitle for this posting is “Three Determinative Articles en route to the Guarantee of Perpetual Peace.” This posting is the second of three installments reviewing Kant’s Toward Perpetual Peace, A Philosophical Sketch (1795).
In the subsection on his first determinative article (rational principle) for perpetual peace, Kant stated his taxonomy of political organization: A state can be classified according to its form of sovereignty (autocratic, aristocratic, or democratic) or according to its form of government (republican or despotic). In a republic, the legislative assembly is representative and is separated from the executive power of the ruler, whereas a despot both makes and executes the laws. Kant believed that, except possibly in some cases of violent revolution, democratic sovereignty leads to despotic government by founding an executive power of a small committee over a large community. Democratic republics are, for Kant, an unlikely species. In contrast, monarchical or aristocratic sovereignty offers the possibility of gradual legal reform culminating in republican government. After all, the Prussian King Frederick II supposedly said that he was merely the highest-ranking servant of the state.
Kant’s first determinative article is: The civil constitution of every state, i.e., its form of government, is to be republican. Kant thinks that only republican constitutions are consistent with the idea of the original contract (individuals giving up some natural rights to a ruler, who enforces peace) and its basic principles of freedom, equality, and dependence upon a single legislative source. The republican constitution has favorable prospects for creating perpetual peace, because a republic’s citizens must vote to adopt the costs of warfare; whereas a despotism’s subjects have no voice in authorizing the dreadful tasks of financing, fighting, and dying in a war.
Each individual’s juridical equality is the right to be constrained only to the extent that others are so constrained. Each individual’s juridical freedom is the authority or power to obey only those laws to which he either has consented or could have consented, either freely or under threat of “being thrown out of the neighborhood” (see the first blog post in this series). Focusing now on the question of “has consented” versus “could have consented,” we see in Kant’s first footnote in his subsection on the first determinative article that “Rechtliche Freiheit … ist die Befugnis, keinen äuβeren Gesetzen zu gehorchen, als zu denen ich meine Beistimmung habe geben können.” In the indicative mood, therefore, obedience is limited to laws “to which I have been able [in fact] to give my consent.” In the subjunctive mood, however, obedience is limited to laws “to which I could have given my consent [even if I did not actually consent].” Only Kant knew whether he meant to use the indicative or subjunctive mood when he wrote that sentence. Either way, it seems clear that the original contract is not one occurrence in the past, but is rather the cumulative effect of a period of negotiation, force, and agreement.
Kant’s second determinative article for perpetual peace is: International law is to be founded on a federation of free states. Peoples (Völker), to the extent that they are civilized enough to form nation-states (Staaten), can be evaluated like individual human beings. Each nation-state that can potentially be injured by other nation-states due to their mere proximity can and should demand from its neighbors that they all enter into a higher-order constitution analogous to that of the constitution for individuals within one nation-state. Such a higher-order constitution must form a league of nations (Völkerbund) but not a higher-order state consisting of blended peoples (Völkerstaat). (In his Universal History of 1784, Kant had written of a Staatsverbindung as that which is opposed to a league of nations. See the March 1, 2019 blog posting.)
Each nation-state contains its own relationship between its lawgiving class and its Volk (be they citizens or subjects), which results in the nation-state’s persisting identity. In effect, Kant adopted an early version of identity politics by saying that nation-states should not be melded or fused together in a higher-order nation-state (nicht in einem Staat zusammenschmelzen sollen). Thus, Kant speaks of his league of nations as a federation of free states.
One should think, Kant writes, that civilized peoples, each of which has already united into a nation-state, would hurry to exit an international system of crudeness, boorishness, animal-like degradation, and warfare in favor of the constitutional order of a league of nations. Until now, however, this has been prevented by each nation-state’s view that its own majesty consists precisely in its own independence, i.e., in the fact that there is no other nation-state that can subject it to external legal compulsion. Live free or die. European and American savages differ only in that the latter eat their enemies while the former exploit them more efficiently.
The idea of federation is practical, Kant thinks, because if fortune should direct one powerful and enlightened people to form a republic (the form of government best positioned to ensure perpetual peace), then this fact would act as a nucleating point that incentivizes other nation-states eventually to join it in a league of nations.
Reason, by itself, presents nation-states with no other way to exit the lawless condition that contains nothing but warfare: Give up wild, lawless freedom; get used to public legal compulsion; and join in a continuously growing, higher-order state consisting of blended peoples. In its purest form, this would be a world republic (Weltrepublik). But to the extent that the counsel of reason is rejected by existing nation-states with their precious notions of independence and majesty, only a surrogate remains, viz., a league of nations.
Kant’s third determinative article for perpetual peace is: The law of world citizenship shall be limited to conditions of universal hospitality. The limitation is that we are not dealing with a Gastrecht (guest law, which would serve as a basis for a foreigner [Fremdling] to claim the status of a temporary “housemate” (Hausgenosse, co-resident, or, presumably, legal resident]), but rather with a Besuchsrecht (visitation law, which is a basis for any foreigner to seek a temporary level of hospitality). Hospitality is the right of an individual, upon his arrival in a country not his own, not to be treated in a hostile fashion during a temporary period of probation, after which he may be turned away if this would not result in his demise. In this manner (by recognizing visitation law) remote parts of the world can come into mutually peaceful relationships that eventually become public law and so bring the human race ever closer to a cosmopolitan constitution.
Compared to such peaceful, cosmopolitan relationships, Kant views the inhospitable behavior of the civilized, preeminently commercial European states in oppressing the indigenous peoples of America, sub-Saharan Africa, the Spice Islands, and Southern Africa as injustice approaching terror. In this regard Kant speaks of “the litany of all evil” (die Litanei aller Übel). At least the more developed societies of the Far East have shown more resistance to European “visitors.”
The idea of cosmopolitan law (Weltbürgerrecht) is not a fanciful or outrageous form of imaginary rights, but is rather a necessary completion (in the form of an unwritten code) pertaining both to civil law (Staatsrecht) and to international law (Völkerrecht) and culminating in public human law in general (öffentlichen Menschenrechte überhaupt or “human rights”), and hence, in perpetual peace.
In conclusion, Kant deferred to no one in harshly criticizing existing European empires; but with his pure, a priori principle in his Universal History that “the natural capacities of rational beings will eventually be developed,” he called for an abstract cosmopolitan utopia that amounted to an empire of sorts. Likewise, with his purest form of political contract theory in his Perpetual Peace, he called for a single, continuously growing, transnational state consisting of blended peoples in a world republic. Thus, at different times Kant aspired to a utopian imperialism and then to a utopian, transnational world republic. He seems ultimately to have realized that the utopian empire and the utopian world republic would forever remain nowhere in the real world. Kant held out hope, however, that his backup plan, a league of nations, would eventually stop warfare.